DCE Stages IV and V
William Regh, S.J., Cogent Cyberethics, Chapter 7
Saint Louis University
October 10, 2024
We can divide Rehg’s method into two major parts.
Steps I-IV culminate with an argument for the consistency or inconsistency of a cyberpractice with Due Moral Regard.
So in Stage IV (midterm question 5) you answer the moral question
with a yes or no answer to MQ(\(q\)), followed by with a cogent argument to support your answer.
Your argument in Stage IV (midterm question 5) should begin using your findings in Steps I–II to support for one of the following claims.
For CP(\(p\))
This part of your argument should end with the exact wording of (i), (ii), or (iii).
If part 1 of your argument ended with (i) or (ii). Immediately proceed to the corresponding conclusion.
If part 1 of your argument ended with (iii). You will need to expand your argument by giving support for one of the following conclusions. Begin with your support, then state one of the conclusions below verbatim.
A dialogically responsible cyberethical evaluation of a given cyberpractice CP proves its public merits by winning reasonable acceptance across relevant perspectives on CP in well-structured networks of communication.
— Rehg (2017, sec. 7.2)
A perspective has relevance insofar as
- those holding that perspective qualify as conscientious stakeholders, or
- those holding it have expertise on an empirical matter—e.g., regarding the actual or likely impacts of \(p\) on stakeholder values and needs—connected with the evaluation of \(p\)
— Rehg (2017, sec. 7.2)
We seek contributions from participants who display dialogical virtues—an openness to reason, willingness to consider other points of view seriously and acknowledge valid points from a range of views. Conversely, to judge a particular participant as unreasonable is to say that that person is either so poorly informed on the matter or so utterly close minded and biased that his or her stance does not really tell us much about public merits.
— Rehg (2018, sec. 8.2)
At this level, we want to know:
- Whether venues of communication exist to distribute relevant information and arguments across mutually relevant publics
- Whether widespread biases, prejudices, mutual suspicion, and the like block an argument’s travel across contexts, or foster the spread of dubious arguments
- Whether misinformation has distorted how arguments travel
— Rehg (2017, sec. 7.2)
One can accept a claim simply by not contesting it, or by acknowledging it as tenable, whereas agreement suggests that one personally believes the claim is true.
— Rehg (2017, sec. 7.2)
Only one of the competing views enjoys wide public merits, finding strong support across all relevant perspectives: that view has presumptive objective validity for all parties, and the burden of argument is on dissent.
Reasonable stakeholders or experts within or across relevant perspectives persist in ongoing debate, adhering to opposing positions that neither side can convincingly discredit; each of the positions thus qualifies as publicly tenable, and may be reasonably held.
Our evaluation is reasonably rejected in most perspectives, making it difficult to consider it tenable; this is the fate of views that are left behind when one position widely prevails, or two or three views appear tenable.
A debate displays a degree of contention, incivility, or structural distortion that precludes confidence that any opinion on the matter qualifies as publicly reasonable.